Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision Both sides next revision
limit_._category_theory [2015/03/16 18:13]
nikolaj
limit_._category_theory [2016/03/07 13:57]
nikolaj
Line 8: Line 8:
 === Elaboration === === Elaboration ===
 A limit of a functor with image in ${\bf C}$, if it exists, is a particular terminal morphism in the functor category ${\bf C}^{\bf D}$. That definition emphasizes the underlying universal property, but it's a little hard to understand what's really going on. The reason is that a morphisms in a functor category is a natural transformation and this means there are a couple algebraic identities which don't get explicitly mentioned in the definition above. If you don't know limits, skip the next section and read the ones using cones first. A limit of a functor with image in ${\bf C}$, if it exists, is a particular terminal morphism in the functor category ${\bf C}^{\bf D}$. That definition emphasizes the underlying universal property, but it's a little hard to understand what's really going on. The reason is that a morphisms in a functor category is a natural transformation and this means there are a couple algebraic identities which don't get explicitly mentioned in the definition above. If you don't know limits, skip the next section and read the ones using cones first.
 +
 +Firstly, keep in mind that in a functor category ${\bf C}^{\bf D}$, the main data of a terminal morphism to $F\in {\bf C}^{\bf D}$ is a natural Transformation $\phi$ from some functor to $F$, through which loads of other naturla transformations factor.  ​
  
 We restate the above definition using a little more prose: The [[diagonal functor]] $\Delta$ maps an object $N$ in ${\bf C}$ to a pretty degenerate functor $\Delta(N)$ in ${\bf C}^{\bf D}$, namely the constant functor $\Delta(N)$,​ which itself returns $N$ on any object. A limit is a terminal morphism from $\Delta$ to $F$, which means that it's a pair $\langle L,​\phi\rangle$,​ with $L$ an object in ${\bf C}$ and $\phi:​\Delta(L)\to F$ a natural transformation,​ so that any other natural transformation $\psi:​\Delta(N)\to F$ factors as $\psi=\phi\circ u$, with $u:​\Delta(N)\to\Delta(L)$ some other natural transformation. Now $\Delta(N)(X):​=N$ for all $X$, i.e. the images of the constant functors comprise only one object. Therefore the arrow $u$ is determined by a single component $u_N$ from $N$ to $L$ and similarly, $\psi$'​s components $\psi_X$ are all of type $N\to F(X)$. The fact that the domains of the components are always the same makes this definition equivalent with that in terms of the cone concept below - a cone is made up from the same data as a natural transformation where all components have the same domain. We restate the above definition using a little more prose: The [[diagonal functor]] $\Delta$ maps an object $N$ in ${\bf C}$ to a pretty degenerate functor $\Delta(N)$ in ${\bf C}^{\bf D}$, namely the constant functor $\Delta(N)$,​ which itself returns $N$ on any object. A limit is a terminal morphism from $\Delta$ to $F$, which means that it's a pair $\langle L,​\phi\rangle$,​ with $L$ an object in ${\bf C}$ and $\phi:​\Delta(L)\to F$ a natural transformation,​ so that any other natural transformation $\psi:​\Delta(N)\to F$ factors as $\psi=\phi\circ u$, with $u:​\Delta(N)\to\Delta(L)$ some other natural transformation. Now $\Delta(N)(X):​=N$ for all $X$, i.e. the images of the constant functors comprise only one object. Therefore the arrow $u$ is determined by a single component $u_N$ from $N$ to $L$ and similarly, $\psi$'​s components $\psi_X$ are all of type $N\to F(X)$. The fact that the domains of the components are always the same makes this definition equivalent with that in terms of the cone concept below - a cone is made up from the same data as a natural transformation where all components have the same domain.
Link to graph
Log In
Improvements of the human condition