Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
seperated_presheaf [2014/10/29 09:55]
nikolaj
seperated_presheaf [2014/12/11 17:27]
nikolaj
Line 7: Line 7:
 | @#FFFDDD: for all     | @#FFFDDD: $s,t\in FU$ | | @#FFFDDD: for all     | @#FFFDDD: $s,t\in FU$ |
 | @#FFFDDD: for all     | @#FFFDDD: $C_U$ ... open cover$(U)$ | | @#FFFDDD: for all     | @#FFFDDD: $C_U$ ... open cover$(U)$ |
-| @#55EE55: postulate ​  | @#55EE55: $\left(\forall (V\in C_U).\ ​F(i)(s)=F(i)(t)\right) \implies s=t$ |+| @#55EE55: postulate ​  | @#55EE55: $\left(\forall (V\in C_U).\ s|_V=t|_V\right) \implies s=t$ |
  
 ==== Discussion ==== ==== Discussion ====
Line 13: Line 13:
  
 ===Elaboration=== ===Elaboration===
-A presheaf in topology assigns a set $FU$ to each open set $U$ of a topological space $\langle X,\mathcal T\rangle$. A [[sheaf]] is a presheaf fulfilling two axioms ('​locality'​ and '​gluing'​) and it's intended to capture the case where $FU$ are sets of sections over a topological space (e.g. the section of a fibre bundle $p:E\to X$, e.g. vector fields) and the arrows $F(i)$ are restrictions of those section to smaller open sets. The definition of a seperated presheaf is the first step towards the definition of a sheaf.+A presheaf in topology assigns a set $FU$ to each open set $U$ of a topological space $\langle X,\mathcal T\rangle$. A [[sheaf]] is a presheaf fulfilling two axioms ('​locality'​ and '​gluing'​) and it's intended to capture the case where $FU$ are sets of sections over a topological space (e.g. the section of a fibre bundle $p:E\to X$, e.g. vector fields, e.g. all 1-forms) and the arrows $F(i)$ are restrictions of those section to smaller open sets. The definition of a seperated presheaf is the first step towards the definition of a sheaf.
  
 **Locality axiom**: To understand the postulate, recall that for sections $s,t:U\to Y$ (or function in general) we trivially have that **Locality axiom**: To understand the postulate, recall that for sections $s,t:U\to Y$ (or function in general) we trivially have that
Line 19: Line 19:
 $s=t\implies \forall(x\in U).\,​s(x)=t(x)$ ​ $s=t\implies \forall(x\in U).\,​s(x)=t(x)$ ​
 and as corollary we have  and as corollary we have 
-$s=t\implies \forall(V\subseteq U).\,​s|_V=t|_V.$.+$s=t\implies \forall(V\subseteq U).\,​s|_V=t|_V$ 
 +.
  
 Sections also fulfill function extensionality,​ which goes in the reverse direction Sections also fulfill function extensionality,​ which goes in the reverse direction
  
-$\left(\forall(x\in U).\,​s(x)=(x)\right)\implies s=t$+$\left(\forall(x\in U).\,s(x)=t(x)\right)\implies s=t$
 and consequently,​ if $C_U$ is a covering of $U$, then and consequently,​ if $C_U$ is a covering of $U$, then
 $\left(\forall(V\in C_U).\,​s|_V=t|_V\right)\implies s=t$ $\left(\forall(V\in C_U).\,​s|_V=t|_V\right)\implies s=t$
 +.
  
 Now if the $FU$'s of a sheaf are to be a sets of such sections over a topological space, then it should be that the maps $F(i)$ between them can be seen as restriction of the function domains. To this end, if $i:V\to U$ is the inclusion of a small open set $V$ in another $U$, require that if $s,t\in FU$ agree on all restricted domains which make up the cover of $U$, i.e. $F(i)(s)=F(i)(t)$,​ then there can be no other way in which they can differ, so $s=t$. Now if the $FU$'s of a sheaf are to be a sets of such sections over a topological space, then it should be that the maps $F(i)$ between them can be seen as restriction of the function domains. To this end, if $i:V\to U$ is the inclusion of a small open set $V$ in another $U$, require that if $s,t\in FU$ agree on all restricted domains which make up the cover of $U$, i.e. $F(i)(s)=F(i)(t)$,​ then there can be no other way in which they can differ, so $s=t$.
Link to graph
Log In
Improvements of the human condition